Desiderius Erasmus (1466 - 1536) was intensely aware of
a need for change and renewal in Church and University, religion and thought.
His demand for a "return to the sources" was an expression of dissatisfac
tion with what he saw around him. In particular, he had inherited from
the Italian Humanists an impatience with what was perceived as the closed
dogmatism of medieval Scholasticism. His satire of Folly suggested the
need for change, stimulating the thinkers of his time to explore new directions.
When Christopher Columbus (1451 - 1506) sailed westwards
in 1492, it was at least partly because he refused to accept the conventional
reasons given for not doing so. He had no idea of the presence of a vast
double continent between Europe and Asia, but he saw no reason for not
trying to make a journey of exploration in a new direction. His exploit
was preceded by Vasco da Gama's journey round the Cape of Good Hope
into the Indian Ocean and it was followed by the better publicized journeys
of Amerigo Vespucci westward. Soon Magellan would set out
on a journey to circum-navigate the world; he died in the Philippines in
1521 but his ship reached home.
The complex events known as the Reformation (and the Counter-Reformation),
provoked mainly by Martin Luther followed by Jean Calvin,
brought about huge changes in European attitudes. The new stress laid on
the Bible, and the rejection of Tradition as a basis for believing the
Church's teachings, left each individual more or less free to search for
new formulations of their faith.
Almost unnoticed in his lifetime, the Polish astronomer Nicolas
Koppernik (in Latin Copernicus) (1473 - 1543) published
in 1543 ideas he had long been maturing, claiming that the earth and other
planets revolved about the sun. His De Revolutionibus contradicted
the theory proposed by the Alexandrian Claudius Ptolemaeus (known as Ptolemy)
in the second century A.D. in which the earth was the static centre of
the universe, with planets and sun revolving around it. Because Ptolemy's
theory had become a vital part of the symbolic cosmology taught by Aquinas
and the Scholastics, it was dangerous to contradict it. It took the life's
work of Galileo to overcome the Catholic Church's fierce hostility,
and even he died before it admitted that the earth moved around the sun.
A cultural revolution of radical proportions took place during
the 16th and 17th centuries, when old ideas and ways of thought were challenged
and replaced at many levels. In philosophy, it evolved mainly out of renaissance
humanism, with its rediscovery of Socrates in Plato's works for ever
disputing static and unsatisfactory dogmas as to what was true or real.
The Greek word for "doubt" or "inquire" is skepsis. After Plato,
the Academy continued to be known for its "scepticism" while a more
extreme form of the same attitude, called Pyrronism after its founder
Pyrrho, was formulated by Sextus Empiricus in about 200 A.D. in works widely
read in the renaissance in Latin translations. Pyrrhonism does not
so much assert the impossibility of knowing anything ("academic scepticism")
as refuse to take sides in any argument involving questions of knowledge,
always suspending judgement in uncertainty.
The fundamental attitude of academic scepticism
denies the possibility of knowing anything for sure. What we perceive with
our senses appears to be something, but we may be perceiving it wrongly.
Doubt was thought by the sceptics to bring tranquility, because the sceptic
knows that he cannot know anything, and does not have to try hard to distinguish
illusion and reality. In response, Stoics and Epicureans tried to establish
in various ways a "criterion of truth" or of certainty but their solutions
failed to satisfy the renaissance.
Scepticism is in some ways a very passive and conservative attitude;
as such, it was adopted by Erasmus in his refusal to follow Luther. He
said that it was better to follow existing practices in the Church since
we cannot know for sure that any other way is better. There can never be
a reply to systematic scepticism because it simply repeats itself, challenging
the bases of language as well as of knowledge.
At the centre of the philosophical debate, then, is the question
of knowing, known as epistemology. The basis for knowledge, according
to Aristotle, was thought to be "experience", the information derived by
our five senses. This was normally accepted in the middle ages. The teaching
of the Christian Church about the invisible realities of God and Heaven
was not considered to be "knowledge" but faith in propositions made known
by divine revelation. There is a famous paradox, derived from a saying
by Tertullian (160 - 240) credo quia absurdum est (I believe
because it is absurd) which has always served to stress the difference
between the unquestionable teachings of Christian faith and the information
derived from direct experience. Human reason applies itself to the latter,
trying to understand; in the end, Aquinas and his followers felt, following
Aristotle, the things of God are not accessible to human reasoning.
The scepticism of Sextus Empiricus appealed to Michel de Montaigne
(1533 - 1592). The division between Catholic and Protestant was by now
established and irreconcilable; he himself was Catholic but others in his
family were Protestant. His early Essays (Books 1 and 2,
published 1580) were in a Senecan Stoic vein, designed to produce philosophical
fortitude in a vain world, in preparation for the painful death from kidney
stones he was doomed to by heredity. But a few years after his "retirement
from the world" in 1570, after reading the newly made (1562 and 1569) Latin
translations of Empiricus, he had a medal made with the Pyrrhonian motto
"Que sçay-je?" (What do I know?) and composed his longest
essay, Apologie de Raimond Sebond which formed part of the
Third Book of essays, first published in 1588.
Sebond was a 15th century theologian whose Theologia naturalis
followed the non-Scholastic tradition of Anselm and Lull, offering rational
proofs of God's existence and giving Man a very high position in the created
order, quite unlike the Protestants who considered humanity to be totally
depraved and corrupt. In the Apologie, Montaigne deals less with
Sebond than with all forms of dogmatism and intellectual pretension. He
is an unsystematic pyrrhonist, but his essay demonstrates how like a animal
Man is, weak in reason, his senses unreliable, his morality irrational.
The world is full of diversity and difference, the whole universe is characterized
by flux and change.
Taken as it stands, the Apologie leads to despair. In
the essays that followed, for the rest of his life, Montaigne tried to
lay the bases for a new understanding of what it was to be human. Old philosophies
had failed to find general solutions, a new search was in order, starting
with the individual's self-study. Montaigne was convinced that every person
is equally and fully human, a mixture of virtue and vice. Since there can
be no one perfect system of anything, diversity and tolerance are essential.
His later essays dwell carefully on the minute details of his own body
an daily life, something that no one before him had done in such "scientific"
detail.
John Florio (1553 - 1625) was born in London of an Italian
Protestant father; he translated Montaigne's essays into English in a creative
way, publishing them first in 1603. Shakespeare read them closely, and
was surely influenced by them in many ways. In King Lear there are
many echoes of Florio's vocabulary, while The Tempest is in part
inspired by Montaigne.
Another of the modern world's pioneer thinkers was born, like
Shakespeare, in 1564, but lived far longer. Galileo Galilei (1564
- 1642) was born in Pisa (Italy) and it is mainly thanks to him that the
Copernican vision of the universe was finally accepted despite fierce opposition
from the scholastics who dominated the Catholic Church. The famous "recantation"
in 1633, where he is said to have declared that the earth was the centre
of the universe and did not move, only to murmur "eppur si muove"
(yet it does move), was prompted by his Dialogue Concerning the Two
World Systems of 1632 where he affirms the truth of Copernicanism.
In 1994, the Catholic Church rather belatedly lifted its condemnation of
Galileo's ideas.
At the heart of the dispute, that marks the end of the ancient
world and the start of the modern, is a confrontation between two different
understandings of "truth" and the ways in which humanity can know it. Aquinas,
like Aristotle, was an intense idealist, not interested in pragmatic verification.
For the ancient Greeks, irregular motion was always seen as a sign of the
imperfection of matter. Under the teaching of the old system, the Moon
and all the "bodies" above it (planets and stars) were considered perfect
in matter, spherical in shape and gliding in perfectly circular orbits,
moving not in search of a greater perfection but guided by an Intelligence
(angel or Mover) in order to accomplish some end by influencing events
in the imperfect world below.
Galileo was not the first to notice that there was something
wrong in the sky, that the planets did not in fact move as they were supposed
to. His response was stronger because he looked through his telescope and
saw comets coming and going, declared that there was change in the heavens,
and rejected the old idea that heavenly bodies and the earth were essentially
different. The earth, he said, belonged among the heavenly bodies because
there was change there as here. What Aristotle said was simply not true.
Another point where Galileo differed from Aristotle lay in his
atomist theories, according to which all matter is composed of the same
basic particles (atoms) arranged in different ways. For the Catholic Church
this was a threatening idea because Aristotle had assumed (following Plato's
theory of forms) that each kind of body had its own essential "substance"
(the "breadness" that distinguishes bread from cake) distinct from the
"accidents" of colour, appearance, taste. The Scholastics had used this
to "explain" the meaning of Jesus's words "This is my Body, this is my
Blood" repeated during the Mass to consecrate the bread and wine. The Catholic
doctrine of Transubstantiation depended entirely on the idea that there
was a "substance" in bread, distinct from its appearance, that could be
changed into the Body of Christ by a priest repeating Christ's words.
Galileo stood for empirical observation of things; he practiced
measuring the motion of slowly falling bodies (metal balls rolling in grooves
down a sloping surface), he established mathematical formulae to represent
the laws he found them following. He was the first to state that once a
body is moving, the law of inertia means that it will continue to
move until some new force either stops it or changes its motion. There
was no need to imagine Intelligences pushing the stars to keep them moving.
Galileo has become the symbol of the modern spirit of free enquiry.
His was a mind full of mechanical curiosity, always wanting to understand
the mechanics of things. Until his age, "explanations" of things
seen in the universe were given in terms of God's will and providence.
Galileo's question was not Why? but How? How does it work? It was a revolutionary
question but contained the dangerous assumption that things and phenomena
are ends in themselves. The "scientific" question never enquires about
the ultimate meaning of a phenomenon; to "explain" becomes merely giving
a mathematical account of the way things happen. God has no place in the
methods underlying this enquiry.
In France, the response to Montaigne's challenge to intellectual
certainty came a generation later. René Descartes (or Des
Cartes, whence the adjective "Cartesian") (1596 - 1650) devoted his first
published work to the role of scepticism in the search for truth. His Discours
de la Méthode ("Discourse on the method of rightly conducting
reason and reaching the truth in the sciences") was published in 1637.
It is cast partly in a personal, autobiographical style. Descartes tells
how he realized after a scholastic education at school that truth could
not be found in the books he had read, or in the old Aristotelian categories;
people had to think anew for themselves. He decides to try to assume nothing,
to establish by systematic doubt what things are completely self-evident
and to build on them by reasoning.
If all knowledge depends on sense-data and reasoning, the integrity
of the individual subject is central. Descartes reached a point where he
found himself convinced of his own existence as a reliable subject: "Je
pense, donc je suis" (in Latin, cogito, ergo sum). The
subject's consciousness of being engaged in rational thought is Descartes's
touchstone of reality and truth. This thought, he believed he could prove,
is a non-physical activity, the work in the body of the mind
or soul, the immaterial "thinking substance" that exists in union
with the body yet is totally independent of it and can exist without it.
The Cartesian "dualism" of body and mind has been much debated.
Then follows his most controversial point: since the mind can
conceive of a perfect being, although the human subject cannot claim to
be perfect, there must be a perfect being, God. Like every thinker in the
seventeenth century, Descartes found himself unable and unwilling to deny
the existence of God. Only now God has become the image of our human idea
of the Perfect, and serves to guarantee the validity of sense experi ence.
Because God exists, truth exists and can be reached by the use of our God-given
reason. Out of this comes the essence of Descartes's "Method": experiment
and deduction.
In 1644 Descartes published his great Principles of Philosophy
in which his main system was developed to the full. The main importance
of Descartes does not lie in his epistemological ideas; the cogito,
the argument for God, the dualism of non-dimensional mind and physical
body, have all been more or less rejected. But Descartes was the first
person to assume that matter is the same and always obeys the same
laws everywhere in the universe. The physical laws governing
the universe can be stated in mathematical-style formulae that owe
nothing at all to human sense-data, and will be equally valid everywhere.
By matter, he means anything that has "extension" (length,
breadth, height) although the particles composing it may be of differing
kinds in different states. Descartes saw too that motion was a fundamental
property of matter that might be varied but never lost.
In the history of European thought, Descartes occupies a central
place. He laid the foundations of the entire "scientific" process that
is still fundamental to today's world. The cosmic vision the scholastics
inherited from Aristotle and the Bible was an ancient one, never subject
to verification by experimentation. Descartes's "natural philosophy" was
essentially a mechanical view of nature, in which every aspect could
be "explained" by mathematical laws.
In England, Descartes was preceded by an almost equally impressive
and important writer, Francis Bacon (1561 - 1626). For England, Bacon was
the great herald of the scientific revolution. This was in great part because
he was a wonderful writer, a master of prose style. His parents were in
the court, and he himself was very ambitious. His mother's sister was the
wife of Lord Burghley, the most powerful man in Elizabeth's administration,
but he did not help Bacon much. Instead, he was encouraged by the Earl
of Essex during the 1590s. He turned against Essex after the rebellion
of 1601. Under King James he rose rapidly in the legal administration until
in 1618 he became lord chancellor. Yet in 1621 he was forced to admit that
he had taken bribes as a judge and had to retire from public life in disgrace.
His public career tells nothing about his enduring significance.
Bacon was schooled in the old rhetorical tradition, memorizing
many quotations from the classics, learning how to use them in disputations,
developing a style marked by many aphorisms (short sayings). His legal
training only encouraged him to develop the art of using rhetoric to persuade
others to think in a particular way, while concealing the opinions of the
lawyer as an individual person. Bacon was a master of words, but was not
interested in expressing personal opinions or experience in the way that
Montaigne was. Montaigne invented the word "essay" for this kind of writing,
suggesting as it does words like "experiment, trial, test". Erasmus's Latin
Adagia were a major influence.
Bacon's Essays are his most widely-read work yet
they are often disconcerting. He first published a collection of ten essays
in 1597, under the title (in the original spelling) Essayes. Religious
Meditations. Places of perswasion and disswasion. He continued to write
and to revise his earlier work, as Montaigne did. In 1612 a second edition
appeared, with the simpler title The Essaies, containing thirty-eight
essays, including nine from the first edition. The final edition, published
in 1625 with the title The Essayes or Counsels, Civil and Morall,
contained fifty-eight essays, twenty of them new and most of the essays
from the 1612 edition much revised.
Bacon, like Erasmus, liked to define himself by opposition
to the old Scholasticism, which for him represented error, confused thinking,
and superstition. Yet in the Essays he is following the scholastic
method of debate, which consisted basically in presenting aphorisms
(short quotations) from various authorities (classical, biblical, or patristic)
to support or attack a given topic. Bacon's elaborate Elizabethan style
lends great elegance and complexity to what are in fact a series of mutually
contradictory aphorisms buried in his text; the contradictions are not
given any direct resolution, the reader must think and judge the issues.
The most well-known quotation from the Essays, and a key
to reading them, is the opening of the first essay, Of Truth:
What is truth? said jesting Pilate, and would not stay for an answer.The reference is to St John's Gospel where Pontius Pilate is judging Jesus who has just said, "I came into the world to bear witness to the truth". Pilate's question is doubly ironic, suggesting that there is no ultimate truth at the very moment when he is in the presence of Jesus who is believed by Christian's to be God's own Truth. No one is going to find anything in Bacon's essays if they cannot echo the words spoken by Pilate without the irony. In the face of so many contradictory opinions, what is the truth about Death, or Religion, or Love, or any of the other topics covered by Bacon? The danger is that, like Pilate, we rush to the wrong opinion and stick there, not "staying" (taking the time) to see the whole picture. Bacon summarizes the heart of the problem:
But it is not only the difficulty and labour which men take in finding out of truth, nor again that when it is found it imposeth upon men's thoughts, that doth bring lies in favour, but a natural though corrupt love of the lie itself. One of the later school of the Greecians examineth the matter and is at a stand to think what should be in it, that men should love lies where neither they make for pleasure,as with poets, not for advantage, as with the merchant, but for the lie's sake. But I cannot tell. This same truth is a naked and open daylight that doth not show the masques and mummeries and triumphs of the world half so stately and daintily as candlelights. Truth may perhaps come to the price of a pearl, that showeth best by day; but it will not rise to the price of a diamond or carbuncle, that showeth best in varied lights.This mixture of hard-to-find truth and attractive lies is the challenge of life. The essay Of Truth ends with another Gospel question, only Bacon changes Christ's words from Luke into a certain prophecy that "He shall not find faith upon the earth". Bacon makes Christ foresee that people will prefer lies to truth, and in his own life Bacon certainly seems to have been more untruthful than many. The main appeal of his essays is the delight of many striking expressions:
The joys of parents are secret, and so are their griefs and fears: they cannot utter the one, nor they will not utter the other. Children sweeten labours, but they make misfortunes more bitter: they increase the cares of life, but they mitigate the remembrance of death. (Of Parents and Children)He that hath wife and children hath given hostages to Fortune, for they are impediments to great enterprises, either of virtue or mischief. Certainly the best works, and of greatest merit for the public, have proceeded from the unmarried or childless men, which both in affection and means have married and endowed the public. (Of Marriage and Single Life)
The stage is more beholding to love than the life of man. For as to the stage, love is ever matter of comedies and now and then of tragedies; but in life it doth much mischief, sometimes like a siren, sometimes like a fury. (Of Love)
The Essays fall under the kind of writings considered
today as "literature" but they are not Bacon's main work. His The Advancement
of Learning (1605) and the Novum Organum (1620) are the two
works by which he influenced his age and became known as one of the fathers
of modern scientific method. He consciously and conspicuously turned his
back on the past and looked towards the future. The Advancement
was first published in English, but Bacon later revised it and translated
it into Latin to give it a European readership as De Dignitate et Augmentis
Scientarum (1623) which was in turn re-translated into English and
published in Oxford in 1640. In it Bacon attacks the ignorance and superstition
of the astrologer-magicians, of the scholastics, and even of the humanists,
because they remain content with flawed and imperfect knowledge, instead
of striving to gain a better understanding of God's works. His basic argument
is that before the Fall, Adam in Paradise possessed "pure and immaculate
Natural Knowledge" by God-given intuition. That instinctive knowledge had
given him the mastery over the Creation he had needed when he gave names
to everything but which was lost with Adam's original perfection at the
Fall.
Bacon insists that knowledge of the universe was not the cause
of Adam's Fall, and that "the Divine nature took delight to hide his works,
to the end that they might be found out. Therefore it is God's will that
humanity should strive to come to an ever more nearly perfect, unified
understanding of every aspect of the natural world. Bacon's fundamental
programme of study he termed "The Great Instauration". It was to
be based on experimentation and step-by-step induction as a scientific
method allowing an ever more perfect form of learning to come into being
and be transmitted.
Until now, the "authorities", the received writers of past ages,
had been seen as the giants on whose shoulders the modern dwarfs stood.
It was Bacon who overturned the giants and said that everything remained
to be discovered. This was an intellectual revolution and recent studies
have stressed Bacon's importance in the whole social revolution of his
time. His rejection of the past and his proclamation of a New Age of science
leads directly to the belief in Progress that has so marked the scientific
age.
Yet Bacon built on Aristotle. The Organon (instrument)
was the name given to Aristotle's six treatises on formal and scientific
logic based on the syllogism. Bacon denounces the syllogistic method of
speculative deduction and advocates in its place a new methodology, a "new
instrument" based on scientific deduction, itself based on direct observation
of phenomena.
Bacon distrusted words and he distrusted the mind; he was in
many ways a sceptic. He demanded that people's minds should be purified
(like the pagan temples at the coming of Christianity) by removing the
various idols that stood for false notions of the truth. This is the most
famous part of the Novum Organum:
(51) The human understanding is of its own nature prone to abstrac tions and gives a substance and reality to things which are fleeting. But to resolve nature into abstractions is less to our purpose than to dissect her into parts.... Matter rather than forms should be the object of our attention, its configurations and changes of configuration, and simple action, and law of action or motion; for forms are figments of the human mind, unless you will call those laws of action forms.Bacon's Idols of the Tribe represent the general tendency of people to mistake words for reality and to think that an abstraction is a reality; he is recalling the medieval conflict between nominalists and realists, and his position has some parallels with the English nominalist William Ockham (1285 - 1347).
(52) Such then are the idols which I call Idols of the Tribe...
(59) But the Idols of the Marketplace are the most troublesome of all: idols which have crept into the understanding through the alliances of words and names. For men believe that their reason governs words; but it is also true that words react on the understanding; and this it is that has rendered philosophy and the sciences sophistical and inactive....
(60) The idols imposed by words on the understanding are of two kinds. They are either names of things which do not exist (...), or they are names of things which exist, but yet confused and ill-defined, and hastily and irregularly derived from realities. Of the former kind are Fortune, the Prime Mover, Planetary Orbits, Element of Fire, and like fictions which owe their origin to false and idle theories....
Bacon reserves his fiercest attack for the Idols of the Theatre,
false ideas which result from speculative thought unchecked by reference
to any kind of empirical evidence or experimentation:
(61) But the Idols of the Theatre are not innate, nor do they steal into the understanding secretly, but are plainly impressed and received into the mind from the play-books of philosophical systems and the perverted rules of demonstration.Bacon was firmly rooted in the Scholastic tradition that he denounced so strongly. One of his main achievements was to propose a clear distinction between Nature and the "supernatural" realm perceived only by Faith. Here he follows Aristotle and Aquinas but the result of his distinction was to deny that faith had anything to say about the physical universe. Knowledge of God comes from the Bible: "Sacred theology must be drawn from the word and oracles of God, not from the light of Nature or the dictates of Reason".
Born in the year that Bacon published his Advancement of Learning,
Sir Thomas Browne (1605 - 1682) lived a very simple kind of life. After
the traditional classical education at Winchester College and Oxford he
travelled in Ireland, then studied medicine in France, Italy, and the Netherlands
at a time when the old book-learning was being slowly challenged by the
new experimental approaches.
He realized that tensions had arisen between science (or natural
philosophy, as it was known) and religious faith. After returning to England
in 1633 he began to compose (in English) a book discussing and trying to
help solve those tensions. He settled in Norwich to practice medicine in
about 1637 and Religio Medici was first published without
his name or permission in 1642. It was very popular and in 1643 an official
edition appeared. It was translated into several European languages and
was widely read, not always with approval among dogmatic churchmen. Browne
explores religious divisions and hostilities; then he goes on to expound
a universal love for humanity in all its diversities. Biblical ideas are
supported by many classical references and a great display of wit.
Browne had read widely in many areas, he was a true "Metaphysical"
in being able to draw metaphors from many sources, classical, biblical,
scientific, and he wrote in as complex a style as Bacon. He was fascinated
by the search for greater truth and during the years of the Civil War he
composed Pseudodoxia Epidemica: or Enquiries into Very many received
Tenents and commonly presumed Truths often known as Vulgar Errors published
in 1646 but several times revised and augmented later. Here he is directly
following in the footsteps of Bacon, who was always critical of the way
wrong ideas were taken for truth. He starts by analyzing the various reasons
for error in ways similar to Bacon's idols: sin, gullibility, fallacy,
credulity, authority, Satan. Then follow six books in which he examines
over a hundred familiar errors in various scientific and historical disciplines.
The Pseudodoxia established Browne's reputation as a very
learned man, capable of informed debate in almost every aspect of learning.
During the 1650s, he wrote Hydriotaphia, or Urn Burial (published
1658) which is now his most widely admired work. Starting with the discovery
of some prehistoric urns containing human ashes, he meditates on the ways
different cultures have treated their dead. This leads to a meditation
on the fragility of monuments, the power of time, and culminates in a realization
that only the Christian hope of Resurrection offers a solution to the threat
of oblivion. The high style of Hydriotaphia makes it one of the
finest pieces of English prose ever written. Browne published Hydriotaphia
accompanied by The Garden of Cyrus, a kind of witty showpiece about
the use of certain numerical motifs employing the number five in classical
buildings and gardens. He also wrote a number of tracts and his private
letters are also popular reading.
Browne's voice is one of those raised to resist the excessive
materialism of Bacon's views, and to insist that faith remains central
to a right understanding of nature since to measure and observe is not
the same as to understand truly. One of the most famous passages of Religio
Medici (Part I section 9) stresses the need for a sense of religious
wonder:
As for those wingy mysteries in divinity and airy subtleties in religion which have unhinged the brains of better heads, they never stretched the pia mater (skin around the brain) of mine; methinks there be not impossibilities enough in religion for an active faith; the deepest mysteries ours contains have not only been illustrated, but maintained by syllogism and the rule of reason: I love to lose myself in a mystery, to pursue my reason to an o altitudo ("O the depths..." Romans 11:33). 'Tis my solitary recreation to pose my apprehension with those involved enigmas and riffles of the Trinity, with incarnation and resurrection. I can answer all the objections of Satan, and my rebellious reason, with that odd resolution I learned of Tertullian, Certum est quia impossibile est (It is certain because it is impossible). I desire to exercise my faith in the difficultest points, for to credit ordinary and visible objects is not faith, but persuasion.It was the continuing human need for the dimension of wonder expressed in Browne's o altitudo that led thinkers later in the seventeenth and in the eighteenth centuries to stress the experience of the sublime.
Now since these dead bones have already outlasted the living ones of Methuselah, and in a yard underground and thin walls of clay outworn all the strong and specious buildings above it, and quietly rested under the drums and tramplings of three conquests, what prince can promise such diuturnity unto his relics... Time which antiquates antiquities and hath an art to make dust of all things hath yet spared these minor monuments. In vain we hope to be known by open and visible conserva tories, when to be unknown was the means of their continuation and obscurity their protection.It ends in a great showpiece of style:
Pyramids, arches, obelisks were but the irregularities of vainglory and wild enormities of ancient magnanimity. But the most magnanimous resolution rests in the Christian religion, which trampleth upon pride and sits on the neck of ambition, humbly pursuing that infallible perpetuity unto which all others must diminish their diameters, and be poorly seen in angles of contingency.It should not be thought that Sir Thomas Browne (he was knighted by Charles II in 1671) was merely a playful stylist. He created the language that expressed what he wanted to say. Among the words that he was the first to use in English are 'medical', 'literary', 'electricity', 'precarious', 'hallucination'. He followed Bacon in his enthusiasm for the new age of experiment and discovery. It is the personal authenticity and breadth of vision that speak through Browne that have endeared him to generations of readers. Not surprisingly, he was a friend of many of the leading researchers of his time.
Pious spirits who passed their days in raptures of futurity made little more of this world than the world that was before it, while they lay obscure in the chaos of preordination and night of their fore beings....
To subsist in lasting monuments, to live in their productions, to exist in their names and predicament of chimeras was large satisfaction unto old expectations, and made one part of their Elysiums. But all this is nothing in the metaphysics of true belief. To live indeed is to be again ourselves, which being not only an hope but an evidence in noble believers, 'tis all one to lie in St Innocent's churchyard as in the sands of Egypt, ready to be anything, in the ecstasy of being over, and as content with six feet as the moles of Adrianus.
The main concern of all the thinkers of this age was truth.
The quest for truth went in two main directions. The truth about the external
world was now seen to be a matter of measurement, while faith and ethics
were inward truths discovered by some kind of inner light and supported
by Reason. Descartes divided reality into Extension (the material world
with its dimensions in space) and Thought (mind or soul). What could be
described and defined mathematically was considered real in the truest
sense. Reality was material, extended in space and moving in various ways.
At the same time, Galileo's atomic theories and Copernicus's heliocentric
model suggested strongly that the impressions received by the senses (sense-data)
might be quite misleading.
The result of this in Descartes was a division between body and
mind (spirit or soul) that could never be bridged. The two essential certainties
that Descartes reached by intuition, that I and God truly exist, have nothing
in common with the mechanical laws governing the objects that the mind
perceives outside of itself. Since the senses are deceitful, they should
not be given room to interfere with the operations of the thinking mind,
of Reason. Descartes's approach is not poetic or symbolic.
This, pushed to its ultimate extremes, leads to the position
stated by Hobbes in Chapter 46 of his Leviathan:
The universe, that is, the whole mass of all things that are, is corporeal, that is to say, body, and hath the dimensions of magnitude, namely length, breadth, and depth; also, every part of body is likewise body, and hath the like dimensions, and consequently every part of the universe is body, and that which is not body is no part of the universe; and because the universe is all, that which is no part of it is nothing, and consequently nowhere.In these words, using concepts such as "corporeal" or "body" which he never really queries or defines, Hobbes is rejecting every kind of speculative approach and every suggestion that there is more to existence than matter and motion. Although he was in name a Christian, his arguments lead straight to atheism. Hobbes had little in common with the concerns and sympathies of Sir Thomas Browne.
Hereby it is manifest that during the time men live without a common power to keep them all in awe, they are in that condition which is called war; and such a war as is of every man against every man. For war consisteth not in battle only, or in the act of fighting, but in a tract of time wherein the will to contend by battle is sufficiently known; and therefore the notion of time is to be considered in the nature of war, as it was in the nature of weather. For as the nature of foul weather lieth not in a shower or two of rain, but in an inclination thereto of many days together; so the nature of war consisteth not in actual fighting, but in the known disposition thereto, during all the time there is no assurance to the contrary. All other time is peace.
Whatsoever therefore is consequent to a time of war, where every man is enemy to every man, the same is consequent to the time wherein men live without other security than what their own strength and their own invention shall furnish them withal. In such condition there is no place for industry, because the fruit thereof is uncertain, and consequently no culture of the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities that ma be imported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving, and removing, such things as require much force; no knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time; no arts; no letters; no society; and, which is worst of all. continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.
That last epigrammatic phrase has provoked immense debate
and helped many thinkers clarify their fundamental opinion about the meaning
and value of human existence.
Hobbes offers a very simple solution. All people need do to avoid
strife is to submit to a single absolute ruler whose laws are decisive
in every matter. For Hobbes, even religious truth is true only because
the sovereign's law declares it to be so. The "social contract" is the
name of this topic, and it developed in 17th century Europe in part as
a result of protestant attempts to apply the biblical idea of "Covenant"
to human society in general. Because Hobbes has such a negative view of
human life (he always insisted that he was born early because his mother
was terrified by news of the Spanish Armada in 1588!) he proposes a form
of contract that sounds like a prison sentence.
Yet the main historical interest of Hobbes's work is not his
concept of absolute dictatorship, which only found its unfortunate fruition
in the 20th century, but the expression he gives to extreme materialist
explanations of sensation and thought. In the epistemological debate about
knowledge and perception, Hobbes's denial of any non-material essential
"I" led him to look for entirely mechanical explanations of the way we
see and respond to the outside world. All perception is the echo inside
of our bodies of motions and vibrations outside of them. Hobbes did not
explain "consciousness" at all but felt no need to postulate an immaterial
soul as an explanation of anything. For Hobbes, the soul belonged to the
same category as ghosts, and he hated ghost stories, considering them to
be utter "nonsense".
In the history of thought, the great battles are often fought
in teams, not always by extraordinary individuals. A response to Hobbes's
materialism was formulated in the various writings of a group of men associated
with Cambridge University during the Commonwealth and Restoration: Benjamin
Whichcote, John Smith, Henry More, and Ralph Cudworth whose The True
Intellectual System of the Universe was the most important expression
of the group's ideas.
While they were opposed to Hobbes, they were also distressed
by the irrational fanaticism and extremist controversy that was tearing
the Church apart. While they reasserted Plato's notion of Forms printed
in the soul enabling us to interpret reliably the appearances perceived
outside ourselves, they believed that human Reason, the Order of the Universe,
and Divine Revelation were in harmony; therefore to seek for Truth with
our reason is to seek for God and to understand the Order of the universe
is to know the mind of God its Author.
Like Milton, they did not accept the pessimistic Calvinistic
doctrine of "total depravity" by which no one could know anything about
God without special saving Grace. Instead, they optimistically believed
that human beings could advance to perfection by using their Reason, which
at the same time would show them how to live virtuously in society. Truth
and Goodness were both natural possibilities for ordinary people in general.
Their calm, reasonable attitude with its appeal to Plato and cool reason
helped prepare the way for the Deism of the 18th century's religious thinkers.
Bacon never finished writing his fable The New Atlantis
modelled on More's Utopia. In it he describes an imaginary Pacific
island of Bensalem with its "Solomon's House" or "The College of the Six
Days' Work" which is a kind of college for the sciences, "dedicated to
the study of the works and creatures of God". He imagines a new academic
society to unite all those concerned to explore the new learning. At the
time, the universities of Oxford and Cambridge were only concerned to teach
the old forms of philosophy and saw the formation of Christian ministers
as their main function.
An independent college had been founded near London in the 1580s
by a London merchant, Sir Thomas Gresham. It had developed a practical
curriculum that included Astronomy, mathematics, anatomy, physics for adult
citizens who wanted to learn more in areas that could help them in their
work. When Oxford came under Puritan control in the later 1640s, teachers
formed at Gresham were brought in to develop the study of the "natural
sciences" there.
Bacon had justified his programme of The Great Instauration
by reference to a restoration of the perfection Adam had enjoyed in the
Earthly Paradise. This theological vision coincided exactly with the optimistic
millenarianism that was being promoted in the early 1640s by Samuel Hartlib,
Gabriel Plattes (in the Utopian work Macaria of 1641), John Dury,
and Jan Amos Comenius. Comenius called his vision "Pansophia", it
was to be the dawn of a new enlightenment spread across Protestant Europe
by which material benefits would accrue from increased knowledge about
the universe. Like Milton and many others, they were convinced that if
England led the way, this new perfection of learning in society would encourage
God to bring in the Reign of Christ and vanquish the old ignorance.
Throughout the Commonwealth, the Baconian vision and the millenarian
optimism of many Puritans worked together to promote the growth of experimental
sciences. Even when the Commonwealth failed, the sense of being promised
an ever brighter future continued, and the very word "Restoration" spoke
of much more than the return of a king. It was felt to allude to the Restoration
of Paradise, the Golden Age often related to the time of Augustus, a time
of peace, progress, and reason.
Finally the Royal Society of London for the Improving of Natural
Knowledge was given its charter in 1662. Not all its members were scientists,
they included Dryden, Cowley, Waller, as well as Sir Christopher Wren (architect
of St Paul's Cathedral after the great fire of 1666). The Royal Society
is generally credited with having encouraged its members to employ a simple
plain style of writing. In this it helped the English language pass from
the elegance of Sir Thomas Browne to a more modern austerity. It also reflects
the way in which poetry, marked by metaphor and wit, was being marginalized
and rejected in favour of a lucid, "prosaic" means of expression.
Locke is one of the most influential thinkers England ever produced.
John Locke (1632 - 1704) was educated in the traditional way at Westminster
School and at Christ Church, Oxford. He was given positions in the university
and in public service, he was also interested in medicine and was physician
to the earl of Shaftesbury but much of his time was spent in study and
writing.
In 1690 he published his greatest work, the Essay concerning
Human Understanding that remains one of the fundamental texts in
the philosophical analysis of "mind". In the same year, he published two
Treatises of Government in which he insists that there is no divine
or absolute right of kings. Contradicting Hobbes, he insists that the king
in a state is bound by the social contract, that the people's consent
to his rule may be withdrawn and a new ruler chosen if the king fails to
serve the best interests of the nation.
He was writing at the time before 1685 when people were trying
to prevent the Catholic prince James Stuart from succeeding his brother
Charles II. After this failed, the events of 1688 forced James into exile
but he did not surrender the crown. Locke was closely associated with William
of Orange and published the Treatises in support of the argument that the
title of king was given by popular consent and could be taken back by regular
process. Many in England had been troubled by the idea of recognizing Parliament's
right to make and unmake kings; Locke writes to justify this course of
action.
In 1695, Locke published another major text, The Reasonableness
of Christianity, expressing a form of natural religion without fixed
creeds or traditions. He was opposed to Catholicism but wished for a very
tolerant attitude towards the various forms of Protestantism. Locke was
a leader in the development of rational Deism. His Thoughts concerning
Education (1693) were immensely popular in the following century and
influenced Rousseau's ideas on the subject expressed in Emile.
The Essay concerning Human Understanding underwent further development
in various later editions, until the fifth in 1706. Locke believes that
God has made us with the capacity to know certain things in certain ways,
which knowledge must be for our good since God wishes us to have it. "My
purpose," writes Locke, is "to enquire into the original, certainty, and
extent of human knowledge; together, with the grounds and degrees of belief,
opinion, and assent." The style is very different from the florid style
of Bacon or the harshness of Hobbes.
Locke's fundamental assertion is that we are born with our minds
a blank, like an empty sheet of paper, tabula rasa; we receive
impressions from outside which our reason then transforms into knowledge.
There is no in-born knowledge. Locke is an empiricist and a rationalist:
"Reason must be our last judge and guide in everything." In many matters
Locke is prepared to say that we cannot know or cannot be sure of knowing
rightly about the outside world. One important word for Locke is idea which
he does not use in the Platonic sense but in Descartes's manner, to signify
"the object of the understanding when a man thinks", mind-dependant.
It was Locke who, after Descartes, decided the direction and
concerns of modern European philosophy. For the writers and thinkers of
the 18th century, Locke was fundamental reading, though perhaps more for
his political views on society than for his difficult theories of knowl
edge. If the 18th century is known commonly as the Age of Enlightenment
or the Age of Reason, it is very largely thanks to John Locke. The
work of Lessing and Kant, of Voltaire and Diderot, and many others, derives
from ideas first developed in England. The successors to Locke in England
are George Berkeley (1685 - 1753), David Hartley (1705 - 1757) and David
Hume (1711 - 1776).
The 18th century looked back with gratitude to the century that
produced Milton, Locke, and Newton. Paradise Lost was the only European
epic that stood comparison with Homer or Virgil. Locke had established
Reason as the basis for all knowledge. Newton was the third great founder
of the Age of Reason. Newton (1642 - 1727) was born into a humble family,
but was able to study at Cambridge and stayed there from 1661 until 1696,
when he was given the post of master of the Royal Mint and president of
the Royal Society. He never married.
Newton was one of the greatest geniuses that Europe ever produced.
His pioneering work in mathematics, dynamics, astro-physics, astronomy,
optics, cosmology is still a fundamental reference today. Only in the matter
of relativism (Einstein) has he been shown to have been lacking. Yet he
wrote major studies in areas such as prophecy and alchemy, as well as theology
and biblical chronology, where today these subjects are not part of a scientist's
normal concerns.
Newton's cosmic view ("Newtonianism") is expressed in three major
works: Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica (1687), the
Optiks (1704) on the nature of light, and Arithmetica universalis
(1707). He established firmly that the cosmos was governed by perfectly
rational laws "of nature" that kept it in a marvelous pattern under God
its Maker whose glory was manifest in its great universal harmonies. This
became the leading ideology of the Enlightenment. Contemporary with Newton,
and in conflict with him in some areas, was the great German Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibnitz (1646 - 1716).
Graham Parry, The Seventeenth Century: The Intellectual and Cultural Context of English Literature, 1603-1700. Longman Literature in English Series. 1989.
Basil Willey, The Seventeenth Century Background. 1934
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, edited by Ted Honderich. Oxford
University Press. 1995.